One of this volume’s core analytical wagers is that bringing constructivist insights to bear on the comparative mapping practices within security politics will shed considerable new light on how these practices order international relations. This chapter’s mandate in this endeavour is to explore and problematize how comparative knowledge underpins international status dynamics and thereby informs and shapes security politics.1 In the process, the chapter will reflect upon International Relations (IR) status research’s comparative practices. Status research is understood here as an umbrella term for all research that explores the causes and consequences of states’ efforts to maintain or improve their position in international social hierarchies. This research agenda has proven highly successful over the course of the last decade in documenting how states often prioritize status over wealth or security (see Larson and Shevchenko, 2003; 2019; Deng, 2008; Wohlforth, 2009; de Carvalho and Neumann, 2014; Barnhart, 2017; Beaumont, 2017; Ward, 2017; Murray, 2018). However, this chapter will expand on the analytical costs of what the editors of this volume correctly highlight as status research’s curious commitment to treating status hierarchies as a mind-independent phenomenon amenable to careful mapping (see also Müller et al, 2022).
That philosophical realism is so dominant within status research is curious because the latter’s conventional definition of status is decidedly constructivist, or at the very least is highly amenable to constructivist inquiry: status treated as ‘collective beliefs about a given state’s ranking on valued attributes (wealth, coercive capabilities, culture, demographic position, socio-political organization, and diplomatic clout)’ (Larson et al, 2014: 7). To the (thick) constructivist, these valued attributes do not come ready valued and thus imply that the quest for status also involves a battle over how status is assessed or status comparisons are made (Pouliot, 2014). Yet, as Paul Macdonald and Joseph Parent’s (2021: 7) recent review essay complains, for all status researchers’ differences their agenda lacks answers to the fundamental (constructivist) questions such as: ‘Who decides which attributes are prized and how?’ By jumping straight to the proxies they identify for policy makers, states and publics, status researchers further presume an intersubjective international agreement around the status hierarchy,2 and foreclose the study of the multiple rival hierarchies that are in use and contested at the same time.3 As a result, status research is dominated by a peculiarly thin constructivism that agrees that status is
This chapter explores some of the unfortunate consequences of status research’s philosophical realism, thin constructivism and commitment to mapping status hierarchies at the expense of studying their construction and contestation. Its goal is to show how this foreclosure can be fruitfully addressed by tapping into IR status research’s own lineage, which can provide the theoretical warrant for studying international status dynamics via the rules underpinning status comparisons and thus status hierarchies. Such a move allows us to pose questions such as how do rules governing status competitions emerge, why do some rules become agreed upon and others contested, and what are the consequences of these processes of rule formation? While developing a framework for studying status dynamics through the production and contestation of rules requires an ontological gestalt switch for conventional status research (which has tended to focus on variance in motivations), this chapter argues that it is possible to do as much while remaining consistent with status research’s core definition of status (collective beliefs about rank).
To make this case, the chapter proceeds in three steps. Section one takes stock of the existing status literature and identifies two common limitations that inhibit the elaboration of a (thick) constructivist – rule-centred – status approach: (1) the psychological underpinnings of much of IR’s status research, which conceives of status as a discrete motivation distinct from security; and (2) the penchant for mapping status hierarchies and thereby eliding the study of the construction of international hierarchies. This bundle of assumptions, I argue, has also led many status researchers to draw an unnecessarily stark line between status and security explanations. I then show how Robert Gilpin’s (1981) influential theorization of prestige can provide the basis for a constructivist account of status – one that does not treat status as a distinct motivation – even if this potential has largely been eschewed by those inspired by his framework. To bring out Gilpin’s latent constructivism, section two then revisits an underappreciated chapter in Nicholas Onuf’s World of Our Making to underline and conceptualize the rule-based nature of status comparisons and status hierarchies. When considered alongside Elena Esposito and David Stark’s (2019) work on the social function of public rankings, the section elaborates why states may compete according to the rules embodied in public rankings even when they consider them to provide an inaccurate picture of reality. Taken together and put into security politics, these works provide a framework for studying how comparisons that ostensibly map the distribution of power can become co-constitutive of status hierarchies and how their symbolic function can become their strategic utility.
From motivations and mapping to rules and ordering
Contemporary status scholarship in IR has many predecessors and relates to security in different and often contradictory ways. For those grounded in social identity theory and psychology, status is a distinct motivation that prompts states to pursue foreign policies that go against their security or economic interests (Barnhart, 2017; 2020; Larson and Shevchenko, 2019). Similarly, those that ground their theory in Thorstein Veblen’s sociology contend that status symbols are constituted by visible, reckless waste (Gilady, 2018) as opposed to prudent or rational utilities. Meanwhile, others draw upon classic political philosophers – for example Hobbes, Machiavelli, Thucydides and Rousseau – to posit that glory, honour or pride are timeless human passions (for example de Carvalho and Neumann, 2014; Gilady, 2017). These approaches differ in vocabularies and frameworks, but they share the assumption that states place an intrinsic value on their status in the international system: actors value status for its own sake. Since status re-emerged as a theoretical and empirical research agenda in the 2000s (Larson and Shevchenko, 2003; Wohlforth, 2009; Volgy et al, 2011), the dominant methodological modus operandi for these approaches has been to show how policies that make little sense from a conventional rational perspective, can readily be explained if one assumes status as a motivation. Status is thus usually juxtaposed with security and deemed a dangerous and irrational pursuit, one that states would be wise to forgo or at least temper. This strand of status research has quickly established how a great deal of international
The problem with this agenda is not the lack of compelling evidence, but how the status/material interest4 binary curtails more sociological inquiries into the status hierarchy itself and focuses instead on parsing the motivations of the actors within it (Beaumont, 2024).5 Using the same conventional definition of status – social position in ranking defined by collective beliefs – it is possible to identify status hierarchies (and their consequences) while remaining ambivalent about whether any actor responding to the hierarchy in question is motivated by status or something else. To take an easy example, the Olympic games provides a paradigmatic example of international status competition: players (representing nation states) are ranked in a hierarchy of position based on their performance in various activities requiring skill. ‘Status’ will assuredly motivate some of those taking part, but it need not: some may compete for the material prizes (sponsorship, government funding), others to please their pushy parents; meanwhile, the state governments involved may not care about status themselves but recognize that their electorates do and invest accordingly (see Ward, 2017). Whatever the motivation for taking part, it has little to say about whether the status hierarchies that result from the games are indeed status hierarchies (collective beliefs about rank). What is interesting about the Olympics is not that it is a particularly important case, but that, because it is self-consciously designed to be a well-functioning status competition, the crucial constitutive features of a status competition are so visible: rules (Beaumont, 2024). Indeed, it is the rules of the game(s) that define a status hierarchy and status competition, not the motivation of players involved. At a minimum, this implies that beyond parsing variance in status motivation (see Renshon, 2017), we could potentially study other sorts of status competition through variance in the rules of the game. After all, although Olympic rules are institutionalized and therefore mostly stable, the rules in most international status competitions are not. The major advantage of studying status competitions through the rules of the game would be that it avoids trapping status research in the dastardly difficult quest to ascertain motivations.
While psychological theories of status assume it to be a distinct motivation that can be parsed from more conventional material motivations, the realist-inspired wing of status research emerging from 19th-century Realpolitik avoids this pitfall. This strand of scholarship posits status (or in its terminology,
As this short discussion indicates, the Gilpin school of status research enables the way in which prestige – ‘reputation for power’ – is determined, is earned and informs world politics to be investigated without being tied to status as a distinct motivation driving anyone or any state seeking it. However, Gilpin’s initial theorization to some extent pre-structured and prematurely narrowed this agenda by asserting that ‘prestige was ultimately imponderable’ and could only be settled by war, which would then temporarily clarify the hierarchy of power. Hence, prestige scholarship has largely been preoccupied by studying how wars have been waged to retain or pursue status/prestige (see Mercer, 2017, for a critical discussion). For instance, Jonathan Renshon (2017) claims that states that suffer from a mismatch between material power and status recognition have been more prone to wage war to remedy their ‘status deficit’ over the last 200 years. Moreover, he suggests that waging war has generally proven effective at improving recognition and therefore is a rational strategy for a status-concerned state. Notwithstanding the debates about the empirical merits of this research (see Røren and Beaumont, 2019; Ward, 2020), taking inspiration from Gilpin, these works have generally paid less attention to how hierarchies of prestige are constructed, and even organized and maintained in peacetime, by establishing agreed upon public rankings of power and thus prestige.
[The] Asia Power Index (API) may have succeeded in meeting these challenges [of measuring power/influence] better than most. Published in May 2018, the API is a remarkably comprehensive and rigorous ranking of the overall power of 25 Asian countries (including the United States and Russia). Countries are assessed along eight weighted dimensions: economic resources (20 per cent), military capability (20 per cent), resilience (7.5 per cent), future trends (7.5 per cent), diplomatic influence (10 per cent), economic relationships (15 per cent), defence networks (10 per cent) and cultural influence (10 per cent). (Khong, 2019: 126, emphasis added)
While the API may indeed provide a useful window into the relative prestige of countries in Asia, Khong (2019: 122–3) remains uninterested in why particular indicators of military power become important or crucial as measure of status/prestige or why each indicator was weighted in the way it was. Moreover, and in line with the assumption of ‘mapping’ comparisons discussed in the introduction, he elides the potential ordering effects of picking one indicator (and thus one principle of comparison) over another, and presumes the existence of an invisible hierarchy of power and prestige that could theoretically be evaluated for accuracy. To reemphasize, there is nothing wrong with such philosophically realist efforts at mapping prestige, but it is also quite possible that such efforts may themselves influence and even co-constitute the status hierarchies they purport to measure.
Indeed, while the API is probably not yet sufficiently significant to have much in the way of ordering effects, as Kerrin Langer’s chapter in this volume reveals, power-mapping practices have been quite influential in structuring the competition for reputation for power (prestige). Indeed, Langer
Who sets the rules of the game?
Ultimately, despite the necessary ontological centrality of comparisons in status and prestige seeking, status scholarship has devoted relatively little analytical attention to studying how states actually compare their status (Mercer, 2017). Rather, as the introductory chapter notes, status researchers tend to ascertain the nature of the status hierarchies without studying how states and other actors themselves go about assessing status. Hence, while these scholars often insist that status is perceptual, intersubjective and cultural (see Renshon, 2017: 33–7), they nonetheless – often tacitly – assume (1) that states agree about the rules of the game and (2) that, as observers, they can ascertain those rules without too much ado. Hence, Renshon measures ‘objective status’ over 200 years via the CINC measure, meanwhile Khong (2019) suggests without critical reflection that the API can serve the same purpose. The result is that contemporary status scholarship is dominated by a thin constructivism that presumes that rules governing international status hierarchies are sufficiently stable and agreed upon for us to be able to study their independent effects – the status seeking it incentivizes – while bracketing the processes of social construction that produce the status hierarchies in the first place. An unfortunate side effect of the tendency for status scholars to map status hierarchies on behalf of the agents of world politics prior to analysis is that both the intrinsic and the instrumental school have largely neglected to empirically investigate or theorize how actors engage in mapping international status (see Mercer, 2017), let alone whether and how those efforts at mapping produce ordering effects. This is unfortunate because, as the editors of this volume note in their introductory chapter, ‘status hierarchies only exist if there is a socially shared practice of comparing status’.
Studying the rules of status competitions
The previous section has undertaken a ground-clearing exercise. It has shown how psychological approaches to status use an analytical strategy that relies upon establishing status as an intrinsic motivation, distinct from security and other material motivations. It then identified how Gilpin’s conception of status as instrumentally useful provided an alternative that could escape this binary (status/material motivations). However, Gilpin-inspired approaches have largely eschewed studying how reputations for power are co-constituted by comparative practices that pretend to merely map. Yet, as Langer in this volume illustrates, these mapping practices can and do influence the object of their assessments by providing a conventionalized – and thus well-shared – understanding of what counts as power. The following section sets out to show how we can study both the social construction of mapping practices and understand how and why they can generate ordering effects. This can be done by marrying the Gilpin’s instrumentalism with an analytical focus on the rules governing any given status competition and on how and why these rules are liable to become conventionalized in public rankings. For the first I draw upon Onuf’s unfortunately overlooked chapter on standing in World of Our Making, before turning to Esposito and Stark’s theorization of why even inaccurate rankings serve useful purposes for status assessments.
To begin, let us first sketch out Onuf’s theorization of the rule-governed nature of interests, which can enable us to differentiate the rules governing status comparisons from other kinds of comparison. For Onuf, at the highest level of abstraction there are only three possible interests and these align with three possible grounds of comparison: what he calls internal, binary and global comparisons. The first, internal comparison, should be immediately familiar as the liberal preference for absolute gains and what Onuf calls an interest in wealth. Though by ‘wealth’ he does not mean just money, but anything of value one can desire and enjoy more of: money, love, knowledge or anything else. For Onuf (1989: 266), this involves comparing ‘any state of affairs in which other people’s attributes, preferences, choices count only as a resource for or obstacle to choice’. For instance, a husband wishing to decide whether to eat porridge or a croissant for breakfast will need to order his preferences, whether it be via taste, cost, health or some other concern. To make this order he needs some kind of rule of comparison, otherwise his preference will be random. What makes this internal, for Onuf, is that others only feature in the comparison as an obstacle or a resource: the husband’s partner may pay (provide resources) for or oppose or endorse one or other breakfast, but that has no necessary relationship to the ordering of preferences in the first place; what others prefer need not be taken into account. Onuf’s second ground of comparison is binary, which Onuf labels interest in security. Here, the grounds for comparison are associated with
Finally, and most pertinently, Onuf theorizes that concern for standing must always be founded upon global comparison. By ‘global’ Onuf means a comparison with more than one other entity, rather than one that is global in the geographic sense. This mode of rationality can be understood as analogous to an Olympics: one seeks to do better than the other(s) at a given game with the ultimate goal of being best. Like binary comparison, this mode of rationality is necessarily relational: one cannot aim to be better or best at something without reference to one or more other participants. However, unlike binary comparison, this mode of rationality requires the construction of a ranking system: ‘The set, or whole, then consists of a series of positions occupying a complete and transitive ordering: first place, second place … last place. Furthermore, the places in such an ordering come with cardinal values. … Only now can she say: I want to be best’ (Onuf, 1989: 267). While also relational, unlike binary comparison, global comparison does not involve wanting what the other has in a zero-sum game, but to want to do better than others in some socially valuable thing(s). In order to say that state X is number one in power, democracy or fly-fishing, one needs to have some criteria: is it most tanks or missiles, most fish or biggest fish that matters? Moreover, in order for the hierarchy to be a social hierarchy and for one to be able to plausibly strategize to move up and avoid moving down, some degree of intersubjective agreement on those rules of comparison will be required. Hence, Onuf explicates how any status hierarchy – defined by collective beliefs to do with rank – necessarily depends upon some shared understanding of the rules of comparison. If there were no rules underpinning high/low status, one would not know how to compete for it (Onuf, 1989: 267) and status seeking would be a crapshoot.
Onuf allows us to rephrase the question facing status researchers: ‘How can we ascertain collective beliefs?’ to ‘How are the rules governing “collective beliefs” about rank formed? How do these “collectives”, whoever they are and wherever they may be, construct their ranking system?’ The difficulty of this task for any single individual may at first make the researcher despair; how can we empirically investigate how these people construct their systems for global comparison. But it is precisely the difficulty involved in constructing a ranking – selecting the right rules or gathering the evidence – that gives rise to the shortcuts provided by society. We tend not to do it ourselves but instead outsource the task and rely upon conventions, that is, socially standardized modes of comparison: for instance, GDP is a widely accepted means of ranking states according to wealth or development, even though many if not most of those using it would agree that it is an imperfect measure. If one simply wanted accuracy, one might be tempted to develop one’s own
Indeed, Esposito and Stark (2019) highlight the broader social function of public rankings (rather than to accurately map reality), which can account for the persistent popularity of inaccurate rankings. For them (2019: 4), public rankings are not popular because they adequately describe the ‘independent world (for which they are inevitably flawed …)’ but because they ‘provide an orientation about what others observe’. Indeed, they contend that public ranking systems – especially conventional ones – are best understood as social technologies that allow us to ascertain – or second-guess with confidence – audience beliefs. While Esposito and Stark do not make the link explicit, they provide grounds for believing that international rankings – when conventionalized – operate as a window into collective beliefs about a state’s status in the phenomenon that the ranking purports to measure. Moreover, if the herd’s assessment can help or harm the rankees, then they would have a Gilpinian interest in pursuing a position in that ranking even if they know it to be inaccurate. Hence, from a status perspective, when mappers debate the accuracy of widely recognized power rankings, they miss the point: it is not the accuracy of the measure but the extent of its use – where, by whom and for what purpose – that makes it valuable for ascertaining ‘collective beliefs’ about rank. Ultimately, Onuf and Esposito and Stark provide a theoretical warrant for studying status hierarchies – and their effects – via the prevalence, contestation and conventionalization of concrete public modes of comparison and ranking.
The US’s SALT strategy: how status became security
To illustrate how public efforts at mapping objective hierarchies conventionalize the rules of comparison enabling actors to make educated and consequential guesses about status, I turn to the case of the Strategic Arms Limitation Talks (SALT). In particular, the case study explores the backstage process through which the United States determined its negotiating position from SALT I to SALT II and specifically how it determined which rules – grounds of comparison – to assess the nuclear balance by, and how and why it settled upon aggregate number of launchers. Besides practical reasons, the US side of the negotiation is selected because it provides a harder case for my approach: Russia’s status obsession is already well documented,
SALT was premised upon the idea that the superpowers shared an interest in reducing the risk of nuclear war by implementing more stable force structures and reducing the costs of strategic arms racing that would leave neither side safer, only poorer. The SALT processes spanned a decade and three presidencies (Richard Nixon’s, Gerald Ford’s and Jimmy Carter’s) and initially seemed successful. ‘SALT I’ led to the signing and ratification in 1972 of the ABM treaty (Treaty between the United States of America and the Union of the Soviet Socialist Republics on the Limitation of Anti-Ballistic Missile Systems), which limited each side to two anti-ballistic missile sites apiece, and the ‘Interim Agreement’ (Interim Agreement between The United States of America and The Union of Soviet Socialist Republics on Certain Measures with respect to the Limitation of Strategic Offensive Arms), which froze for five years the level of submarine-launched ballistic missiles (SLBMs) and land-based intercontinental ballistic missiles (ICBMs) at 1972 levels. The SALT II process would eventually lead to the SALT Treaty (Treaty between the United States of America and the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics on the Limitation of Strategic Offensive Arms), which limited both sides to 2,250 strategic nuclear missiles, and 1,320 missiles equipped with multiple re-entry vehicles (MIRVs). However, the SALT II Treaty took over six years and three US presidents to negotiate and, while it was eventually signed in 1979, it never reached the Senate for ratification because the administration cancelled the vote following the Soviet invasion of Afghanistan. The conventional story has it that SALT II was hamstrung by fears of cheating, a mutual obsession with letting the other side achieve relative gains and thereby enabling them to gain political or military advantages in crisis situations. If this were the case, we would expect that the negotiations strategy of the United States would use systems of comparison by which to assess dyadic outcomes: political (the ability to make the other side back down) or military (for example, the ability to ‘win’ a nuclear war).
Everyone agrees that one of our most fundamental objectives in SALT Two is equality. The real question is, how do we define equality. Do we mean (1) equality in first-strike capability, (2) equality in second-strike capability, (3) equality in numbers of launchers and re-entry vehicles, or (4) equality in assured destruction capability. (FRUS, 1973: 50)
In fact, during SALT I talks, as national security advisor to the president, Henry Kissinger strongly opposed demands for an agreement with equal numerical aggregates. He argued that not only did the various US capabilities that fell outside the agreement (MIRVS, forward-based systems such as bombers in Europe) offset any numerical disparity, but, given that the US lacked plans to build either new SLBMs or ICBMs, any freeze on the Soviet side would be to the US’s advantage. Kissinger would defend SALT I along similar lines throughout SALT II. Thus, it was better to limit the Soviets than do nothing; the US would make relative gains regardless of the perception of inequality. Ultimately, the military did not get their way: the interim agreement that emerged out of SALT I froze the SLBMs and ICBMs at levels whereby the US were permitted fewer submarine and land-based launches. Kissinger would see this result as a remarkable negotiating feat. As he put it, the US had not been ‘stopped’ from doing anything they had planned, while the Soviet’s build-up had been halted. In fact, Kissinger considered it ‘miraculous’ that the US had managed to limit submarines and ICBMs ‘when we had next to no chips’ (FRUS, 1972: 957). Here we can clearly see how Kissinger’s concern for relative gains did not necessarily mean being allowed more launchers than the Soviets under the treaty or even the same number, but was calculated relative to what would have transpired without a treaty.
Inherently, this kind of decision is simple to make. The question is whether militarily, diplomatically, and politically, you want to move rapidly toward the Soviet proposal of giving the U.S. inferiority in numbers. This would be very difficult to justify. Unequal numbers would not have much Congressional support, and would violate the Jackson Amendment which requires equal numbers. It would be difficult to persuade the American public that any position other than equal aggregates, especially as our going-in position, is the correct one. (FRUS, 1974b: 330)
Note the role of the Jackson Amendment here in providing a plausible window into how domestic audiences would assess the balance and therefore a window into how the US reputation for nuclear power among domestic audiences would be affected by the agreement. It was named after the hawkish senator, Henry Jackson, who had publicly spoken out against the SALT I Interim Agreement’s provisions, arguing that the freeze froze the United States into a position of ‘sub-parity’ and would put the United States at a disadvantage (New York Times, 1972). Jackson thus sought to attach a Congressional understanding to the interim agreement. The Jackson Amendment, as it became known, demanded that any future SALT agreement must have ‘equal numbers of intercontinental strategic launchers taking account of throw weight’.
While the amendment itself was non-binding and the government would later consider breaching it, by accepting the amendment, they legitimated the criterion of aggregate number of launchers as a means of comparing the nuclear powers arsenals in SALT II, and therefore of how equality should be assessed. Hence, despite its inadequacy as a measure of nuclear balance, which Schlesinger and other advocates of equal launchers freely admitted backstage (for example, FRUS 1974b: 332; FRUS, 1974c: 374), it served the purpose that Esposito and Stark (2019) attribute to public rankings: providing an ‘orientation about what others observe’, in this case what, or perhaps how domestic audiences would assess the outcome of a future strategic arms limitation treaty. Indeed, Jackson’s amendment was frequently used as a reference point and evidence for gauging how domestic audiences would assess a treaty (see FRUS 1974a: 364; 1974b: 330).
However, numerical equality was not the only grounds of comparison the administration expected the domestic audience to use to assess SALT II, the fallout from SALT I led them to believe it was how their allies would assess the treaty. For instance, during his backstage campaign for prioritizing
Hence, between SALT I and SALT II equality in aggregates became a priority in the negotiations and this was justified primarily in reference to how key audiences would assess the outcome of the treaty. As I have highlighted elsewhere (Beaumont, 2024), the prioritization of exact equality of aggregates, against their own strategic assessments, slowed down negotiations and removed a bargaining chip from both hawks, who aspired to limit the Soviet heavy bombers, and doves, who wished to achieve significant cuts in the arsenals.
Conclusion
The preceding discussion and vignette have sought to speak to the volume’s core theoretical concerns: how can comparative knowledge become salient in international security politics, and how and why should IR research foreground comparative practices? First, the vignette illustrated how public efforts at objectively mapping the nuclear balance – by counting launchers – could be turned into a rule for making educated guesses about the status implications of a potential SALT agreement. Indeed, as we saw, the Japanese foreign minister’s view of SALT I and the Jackson Amendment served as compelling
Finally, this chapter also allows us to mount a defence of the dogmatic army general of popular imagination. Generals are always preparing to fight the last war, the old aphorism runs. As conservative as they are dogmatic, they prepare to attack on horses when they should practise sitting in trenches. This tendency is usually deemed at best inefficient and at worst tragic. Yet, the preceding analysis can shine a more sympathetic light on our imaginary generals. Deterring enemies requires they appreciate the implications of waging war. Maintaining allies requires they appreciate the potential of one’s military power. Indeed, deterrence and deference do not depend upon what would really happen in war. Instead, they are social outcomes: they depend upon what others expect would occur and this may not be the same thing. If your enemies and allies are preparing for the last war, then deterrence of the enemy and ally loyalty will require the prudent general to do so too. Indeed, although the US military and Secretary of Defense accepted that the relative aggregate number of launchers was a suboptimal means of assessing the nuclear balance and the treaty, they could
This research was undertaken with the help of funding from the Research Council of Norway’s WARU project (project number: 300923).
It should be noted that given collective beliefs are unobservable and famously difficult to measure, status research’s commitment to philosophical realism bequeathed a formidable task. As Gilpin (1981: 33) noted, prestige is so difficult to assess that it was ultimately ‘imponderable’.
Some readers might object that social identity theory (see Larson and Shevchenko, 2003; 2010; 2019) captures this with social creativity. However, within its rendering, social creativity is a strategy for attempting to change a pre-existing status hierarchy that is widely shared, it does not imply that different actors understand the international hierarchy differently in the first place.
Often but not always conflated with the rational/irrational binary and warning against the wasteful pursuit of status (see Mercer, 2017).
See Towns (2010), Pouliot (2014), Naylor (2018; 2022), Beaumont (2021), Dunton (2020) and Røren (2023) for notable exceptions to this tendency.
Nor does it mean that the protagonists involved did not have ulterior motives. For instance, General Snowcroft wrote to Kissinger that he suspected ‘that the JCS don’t want an agreement and will pursue any convenient argument to prevent it’ (FRUS, 1976: 572).
References
Beaumont, P. (2017) ‘Brexit, retrotopia and the perils of post-colonial delusions’, Global Affairs, 3(4–5): 379–90.
Beaumont, P. (2021) Performing Nuclear Weapons: How Britain Made Trident Make Sense, Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.
Beaumont, P. (2024) The Grammar of Status Competition: International Hierarchies and Domestic Politics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Barnhart, J. (2017) ‘Humiliation and third-party aggression’, World Politics, 69(3): 532–68.
Barnhart, J. (2020) The Consequences of Humiliation: Anger and Status in World Politics, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Buarque, D. (2023) Brazil’s International Status and Recognition as an Emerging Power Inconsistencies and Complexities, Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.
De Carvalho, B. and Neumann, I.B. (eds) (2014) Small State Status Seeking: Norway’s Quest for International Standing, London: Routledge.
Deng, Y. (2008) China’s Struggle for Status: The Realignment of International Relations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Duque, M.G. (2018) ‘Recognizing international status: a relational approach’, International Studies Quarterly, 62(3): 577–92.
Dunton, C. (2020) ‘Willing to serve: empire, status, and Canadian campaigns for the United Nations Security Council (1946–1947)’, International Journal, 75(4): 529–47.
Esposito, E. and Stark, D. (2019) ‘What’s observed in a rating? Rankings as orientation in the face of uncertainty’, Theory, Culture & Society, 36(4): 3–26.
Foreign Relations of the United States (FRUS) (1972) ‘327: Conversation among President Nixon, Senator John Stennis, the President’s Assistant for National Security Affairs (Kissinger), the Assistant to the President (Haldeman), and the President’s Deputy Assistant for Legislative Affairs (Korologos) Washington, June 13, 1972’, pp 957–61 in FRUS 1969–1976, vol. 32, SALT I, 1969–1972.
FRUS (1973) ‘14: Minutes of a Meeting of the National Security Council Washington, March 8, 1973, 10:10–11:30 p.m.’, pp 45–60 in FRUS 1969–1976, vol. 33, SALT II, 1972–1980.
FRUS (1974a) ‘81: Minutes of a Meeting of the National Security Council Washington, October 18, 1974, 3:40–5:45 p.m.’, pp 349–67 in FRUS 1969–1976, vol. 33, SALT II, 1972–1980.
FRUS (1974b) ‘77: Minutes of a Meeting of the National Security Council Washington, October 7, 1974, 2:55–4:35 p.m.’, pp 321–37 in FRUS 1969–1976, vol. 33, SALT II, 1972–1980.
FRUS (1974c) ‘85: Memorandum from the President’s Assistant for National Security Affairs (Kissinger) to President Ford Washington, undated’ [c. 27 October 1974], pp 373–79 in FRUS 1969–1976, vol. 33, SALT II, 1972–1980.
FRUS (1976) ‘120. Message from the President’s Assistant for National Security Affairs (Scowcroft) to Secretary of State Kissinger Washington, January 22, 1976’, pp 570–2 in FRUS 1969–1976, vol. 33, SALT II, 1972–1980.
Gilady, L. (2017) ‘Triangle or “trilemma”: Rousseau and the “Kantian Peace”’, Journal of International Relations and Development, 20(1): 135–61.
Gilady, L. (2018) The Price of Prestige: Conspicuous Consumption in International Relations, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Gilpin, R. (1981) War and Change in World Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Khong, Y.F. (2019) ‘Power as prestige in world politics’, International Affairs, 95(1): 119–42.
Larson, D.W., Paul, T.V. and Wohlforth, W.C. (2014) ‘Status and world order’, in T.V. Paul, D.W. Larson and W.C. Wohlforth (eds) Status in World Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp 3–29.
Larson, D.W. and Shevchenko, A. (2003) ‘Shortcut to greatness: the new thinking and the revolution in Soviet foreign policy’, International Organization, 57(1): 77–109.
Larson, D.W. and Shevchenko, A. (2010) ‘Status seekers: Chinese and Russian responses to US primacy’, International Security, 34(4): 63–95.
Larson, D.W. and Shevchenko, A. (2019) Quest for Status: Chinese and Russian Foreign Policy, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
MacDonald, P.K. and Parent, J.M. (2021) ‘The status of status in world politics’, World Politics, 73(2): 358–91.
Mercer, J. (2017) ‘The illusion of international prestige’, International Security, 41(4): 133–68.
Murray, M. (2018) The Struggle for Recognition in International Relations: Status, Revisionism, and Rising Powers, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Müller, T., Albert, M. and Langer, K. (2022) ‘Practices of comparison and the making of international orders’, Journal of International Relations and Development, 25(3): 834–59.
Naylor, T. (2018) Social Closure and International Society: Status Groups from the Family of Civilised Nations to the G20, London: Routledge.
Naylor, T. (2022) ‘Social closure and the reproduction of stratified international order’, International Relations, 36(1): 23–39.
New York Times (1972) ‘Jackson’s SALT Ploy’, New York Times, 7 August, p 26.
Onuf, N. (1989) World of Our Making: Rules and Rule in Social Theory and International Relations, Colombia, SC: University of South Carolina Press.
Pouliot, V. (2014) ‘Setting status in stone: the negotiation of international institutional privileges’, in T.V. Paul, D.W. Larson and W.C. Wohlforth (eds) Status in World Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp 192–215.
Renshon, J. (2017) Fighting for Status, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Røren, P. (2023) ‘The belligerent bear: Russia, status orders, and war’, International Security, 47(4): 7–49.
Røren, P. and Beaumont, P. (2019) ‘Grading greatness: evaluating the status performance of the BRICS’, Third World Quarterly, 40(3): 429–450.
Towns, A.E. (2010) Women and States: Norms and Hierarchies in International Society, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Volgy, T., Corbetta, R., Grant, K. and Baird, R. (2011) Major Powers and the Quest for Status in International Politics: Global and Regional Perspectives, New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
Ward, S. (2017) Status and the Challenge of Rising Powers, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ward, S. (2020) ‘Status from fighting? Reassessing the relationship between conflict involvement and diplomatic rank’, International Interactions, 46(2): 274–90.
Wohlforth, W. (2009) ‘Unipolarity, status competition, and great power war’, World Politics, 61(1): 28–57.
Zarakol, A. (2017) ‘Theorizing hierarchies: an introduction’, in A. Zarakol (ed) Hierarchies in World Politics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp 1–15.